Mi primera participación en el gran blog de Jack Balkin, Balkinization https://balkin.blogspot.com/
revisando críticamente uno de los últimos libros del amigo y maestro Cass Sunstein
Back to the
sources: How to interpret the Constitution, according to Cass Sunstein (Part
I)
Roberto Gargarella
Back to sources
In what follows, I shall present and critically examine
the book How to Interpret the Constitution, recently published
by the influential jurist Cass Sunstein. I shall divide my study into two
parts: the first one, mainly descriptive, where I shall present the book under
analysis; and the second one, more evaluative, where I shall offer a critical
review of Sunstein’s work.
Sunstein’s new book is a simple, brief, and exciting
work through which the Harvard professor deals with a complex subject, such as
constitutional interpretation -perhaps the most crucial subject in the theory
of law. In order to explore this challenging issue, Sunstein invokes authors,
concepts and principles he had already discussed and defended long ago. In this
sense -one could claim- Sunstein "returns to the sources" of his
academic career.
This “return to the sources” may be considered a cause
for celebration because many of those bases -I shall maintain- were very good.
They hark back to a Sunstein committed to robust ideas of democracy, social
justice, and equality. In any case, despite the attractiveness of the main
theme under study, and the interesting approach proposed by Sunstein on the
subject, the balance of the work is uneven: the text is as attractive in some
of its conclusions as it is fragile in some of its foundations.
Initial questions
Sunstein's undertaking in this new book is as limited
as it is valuable: to deepen the reflections on the theory of constitutional
interpretation, which he had already advanced decades ago. His main objective is
to answer a fundamental question, which is made explicit at the beginning of his
work: How to choose a theory of constitutional interpretation? His attempt to
respond to this question is based on some relevant assumptions, beginning by
the one that says that "the Constitution does not contain the instructions
for its interpretation" (Sunstein, 2023, p. 9). Another crucial assumption,
presented in Chapter 1 of the book, is the idea that there are several
interpretive theories "in competition with each other". More
precisely, for Sunstein, there are many and varied interpretive theories that
have sufficient standing to be considered "candidates" for
interpreting the Constitution.[1]
Through his book, Sunstein presents and explores some of these theories, including
the following: textualism, semantic originalism, intent originalism, Lawrence
Solum's "public meaning" originalism, expectations originalism, John
Ely's protection of democracy, traditionalism, Ronald Dworkin's moral readings,
Thayerism, common law constitutionalism, and Adrian Vermeule's common good
constitutionalism.
Faced with the crucial question of "which theory
to choose," Sunstein offers a plain answer, which is the following:
"Judges (and others) should choose the theory that would make the American
constitutional order better rather than worse" (Sunstein, 2023, p. 8).
This answer -he claims- is intended "to emphasize that when people
disagree about constitutional interpretation, they disagree, in reality, about
what might make the constitutional order better or worse" (ibid, 8).
Immediately after offering this preliminary answer,
Sunstein accounts for two possible replies. First: "Who decides what makes
the constitutional order better or worse?" He responds: "Anyone
trying to choose a theory of interpretation. Judges; legislators; presidents;
you; me; us... That is all there is. There is no one else" (ibid. 9). The
second challenge concerns the fundamental question of how to determine what
makes the constitutional order "better or worse." Sunstein devotes
almost the entire remainder of this work to this question. In the following
section, I will delve into the answer offered by Barack Obama’s former advisor.
Reflective equilibrium and "fixed points"
According to Sunstein, judges ("and others”)
should determine which interpretive theory to adopt through "a kind of
reflective equilibrium," such as that proposed by John Rawls in his A
Theory of Justice. Rawls' idea of "reflective equilibrium"
involved shaping "moral judgments" (in Rawls' case, the
"principles" of his "theory of justice") out of a series of
deeply held intuitions and convictions - the "fixed points" Sunstein
speaks of here. Ideas, for example, such as the one that says that torturing a
child is wrong or that slavery is unacceptable. From those “fixed points” that
we can consider as "morally sound" (widely held and accepted by a
vast majority of people), the aim is to shape a general theory (a theory of
justice, in the case of Rawls; a theory of interpretation, in the case of
Sunstein). The idea is: we first choose certain "fixed points" that
define our community’s legal practice and then, and from there, we select, through
a process of “reflective equilibrium”, the interpretive theory that will allow
us to fit best, and make consistent, those "fixed points".
In this book, Sunstein not only invites us to think
about what the "fixed points" of American law are, but he also offers
us, in a very open way (coming “out of the closet”, he says), a relatively
complete list of "fixed points" –“fixed points” that, in his personal
opinion, are part of the "solid rock" of his country's law. The most
obvious and important of this “fixed points” is the Supreme Court decision in Brown
v. Board of Education. I am referring, obviously, to the Court’s decision
against racial segregation in schools, through which the tribunal contributed
to ending the unfortunate era marked by the principle of "separate but
equal".[2] Along with that paradigmatic
decision, Sunstein adds other "fixed points" of U.S. law, which
include the following:
*decisions that invalidated discrimination based on
gender.
*a powerful protection for political speech.
*the right of married couples to use contraceptives (Griswold
v. Connecticut).
*the discretion given to administrative agencies.
*The idea that gerrymandering can be judicially
reviewed and limited.
*regulation of the use of money in politics (controls
on campaign spending, etc.).
*The idea that political measures, such as maximum
work hours or minimum wages, are not constitutionally prohibited (contra-Lochner),
etc.
Which interpretative theories
should be discard?
For Sunstein, once we have a series of "fixed
points" on which to rely, we are then in a position to determine, through
a process of "reflective equilibrium," which interpretive theories do
their job well, and which ones do not.
Sunstein begins this evaluative endeavor by scrutinizing
two enormously influential interpretative theories, which are, in principle, in
tension with each other: a conservative theory, namely originalism, which
invites us to "look back" (to the origins of the law) when
interpreting the Constitution; and an alternative one, which suggests a
principle of substantial (democratic) deference from judges to legislators -what
we will call, for now, "Thayerism" (the deferential interpretative
approach advanced by James Thayer).[3]
Sunstein proposes to "test" those two influential theories (but also
the favored method of "reflective equilibrium") by asking the
following question: Are those interpretative theories able to properly accommodate
the favored "fixed points”?
For Sunstein, originalism is unable to accommodate cases
such as Brown v. Board of Education; or the idea that the Constitution
does not prohibit maximum hours or minimum wages; or the principle according to
which political speech deserves special protection. This is because
originalism, at least in its standard version, considers that the meaning of
the Constitution was "fixed" at the (original) time it was drafted,
where, for example, a robust notion of private property prevailed (a robust
notion that were incompatible with the advances imposed by the New Deal). This
was a time, in addition, where constitutionalism seemed to coexist with
situations of serious racial segregation (the foundations of the principle of
"separate but equal" were laid there).
Interestingly, Sunstein also shows that his proposed method,
namely “reflective equilibrium," not only suggests us to discard or resist
conservative interpretative theories such as originalism, but also progressive
ones, such as Thayerism. In fact, "Thayerism" - the
"deferential" conception- would also be misplaced in the face of his proposed
"fixed points". More precisely, this "progressive" position
would be incapable of accommodating the same "fixed points" that
originalism was unable to accommodate. For instance, "Thayerism"
could not account for Brown given that the principle of "separate
but equal" cannot be simply presented as "manifestly wrong" or
unquestionably contrary to the Constitution (indeed, that is why such a
principle enshrining racism survived for decades, and withstood strict
"judicial scrutiny"). Similarly, it would be also unclear why we
should consider to be "manifestly inconsistent with the Constitution"
a rule that did not ensure a special protection to political speech.
According to Sunstein, those results (the rejection of
both originalism and Thayerism) speaks well of the proposed method of
“reflective equilibrium”. The suggested method -one could claim- does not appear
as a mere rationalization of one’s preferences: it is a proposal that induces
us to preserve or discard positions based on criteria that are independent of
one's ideological preferences. In any case, we still need to go one step
further. The question that we now face is: can we say something else, regarding
which interpretative theory to adopt (rather than discard)?
What interpretative theory should
we adopt?
In order to answer this last and decisive question, Cass
Sunstein resorts to two “additional fixed points": the deliberative
conception of democracy and the anti-caste principle. These are -in his view- two
abstract "fixed points", which come from theory, but that are at the
same time related to the very foundations of (American) constitutionalism. Moreover,
these are two ideas that are closely connected to the author's theoretical
trajectory: Sunstein discussed and defended both views in many of his early works,
30 years ago (see, for example, Sunstein, 1993; Sunstein, 1994).
On the idea of "deliberative democracy,"
Sunstein argues that it is a notion that "philosophers, political
scientists, historians, and academic lawyers" have elaborated and
recognized as closely linked to the more profound tradition of American
constitutional law (Sunstein, 2023, p. 162). According to Sunstein, such a
notion "plays a high premium on reflection and reason-giving" within
an institutional framework where voters have enormous (ultimate) control over
the most important public issues, and where majority rule exists but "is
not enough." The results, in a deliberative democracy, "must…be
justified by reasons" (see, also, Sunstein 1984). According to the author,
it is his commitment to deliberative democracy that in the end explains many of
the propositions presented above as his "fixed points": the solid
legal protection he advises for political discourse; his support for basic New
Deal measures; his defense of initiatives that restrict or regulate the use of
money in politics; his opposition to political gerrymandering, etc.
On the anti-caste principle, Sunstein tells us that it
is a principle that "forbids the creation of second-class citizenship, and
which informs existing constitutional law concerning equality, particularly in
the domain of discrimination based on race, sex, and sexual orientation"
(ibid., 163). Moreover, it is a vision -he claims- linked to the republican
political philosophy of the "founding era" - a principle that Justice
Harlan took up and summarized in his famous vote in Plessy v. Ferguson when
he proclaimed "There is no caste here" (ibid.). According to
Sunstein, the anti-caste principle is the one that appears behind his defense
of "fixed points" such as Brown; or the one that leads him to
uphold the invalidation of gender discriminatory laws; and also the one that
allows him to support affirmative action policies; etc.[4]
With the presentation of these two additional
"fixed points", we would approach to the end
of Sunstein’s proposed exploration in the area of constitutional interpretation.
At this point -he could claim- we know the diversity of existing interpretive
theories; we know that all of them can be, in principle, defended; we also know
that none of those theories is, in itself, correct. And, at the same time -he
could add- we have learned that there is a method (“reflective equilibrium”) that
helps us navigate between these differences, and distinguish between better and
worse interpretative theories (theories more or less capable of "making
the law better"). That proposed method would require us to recognize the
"fixed points" of the law of our country, and then rank the different
theories according to their ability to "accommodate" those
"fixed points." This -he would conclude- can be done with the
additional help of two "additional fixed points", of a theoretical
nature, but anchored in the country's legal tradition: deliberative democracy
and the anti-caste principle. Sunstein does not go beyond that point. He
admits it openly: “You might me disappointed to hear that my goal is not to
answer [ the question about the best approach to constitutional
interpretation is]” (Sunstein 2023, p. 16). What he tried to do
through the book is to “understand what those who disagree about theories of
interpretation are actually disagreeing about, and offering an account of how
to choose among competing theories” (ibid.). That would be it: the end of the
journey.
………………………………………………………………………………………….
Back to the
sources: How to interpret the Constitution, according to Cass Sunstein (Part
II)
Some critical notes
In the first part of this paper, I described some of
the central features of Cass Sunstein's new book, How to interpret the
Constitution. In that initial part, I referred to the different
interpretative theories presented by Sunstein in his book, and also to the
method he proposed for selecting a theory of constitutional interpretation from
among them. The method in question was the Rawlsian "reflective equilibrium",
built on the basis of certain "fixed points" or paradigmatic judicial
cases (say, in the case of American law, judicial decisions such as Brown or
Griswold), and also with the help of other theoretical "fixed
points" (in his proposal, deliberative democracy and the "anti-caste
principle"). Having completed that descriptive introduction, I will now
present the second part of my analysis, which will be of a more evaluative and
critical nature. I will first make two brief introductory remarks, and then
move to a more substantive examination of Sunstein’s new work.
I begin with a minor reference to the place of this
book within Sunstein's vast oeuvre. I want to call the attention to the fact
that book was published in August 2023 (i.e., three months before the date I am
writing this comment), and also that the bookselling platforms already warn us
that the author has published or confirmed the publication date of (not one or
two, but) nine other books (six of which would be novel, and not the mere
translation or expansion of previous works). This little note is not merely
anecdotal but symptomatic of a circumstance that, for many, has distanced us
somewhat from Sunstein's work. I am referring to the author’s rather excessive disposition
to produce new books, which usually (and inevitably) comes hand in hand with
the publication of very unpolished works, or texts that repeat the same ideas,
although through new examples. Undoubtedly, Sunstein is an author who, after
decades, continues to be at the forefront of contemporary law: he has already
contributed to our common knowledge through many new and provocative ideas
-ideas that have helped us to progress in the study and critical reflection about
the law. The problem is that this lucid and innovative work has been losing
attractiveness and thickness over the years.
On the other hand, and now in favor of this particular
new book, I would say that Sunstein’s “return to the sources” is interesting,
because it allows us to re-encounter the "old Sunstein", who had made
excellent contributions to law. That “old Sunstein” was the one who produced
exciting papers like "Beyond the Republican Revival" or highly
illuminating books like After the Rights Revolution or The Partial
Constitution. Sunstein was, at that time, a progressive democrat who favored
the egalitarian philosophy of John Rawls and defended Ronald Dworkin’s legal
philosophy -theories that he would later set aside, perhaps too quickly.
Sunstein's early works were supported by a broad-based and attractive conception,
whose parts were mutually reinforcing. That conception included a republican
reading of legal history (based on a controversial but exciting reading of the
works of James Madison and Thomas Jefferson), and a deliberative conception of
democracy (like the one advanced by Jurgen Habermas or Jon Elster).
On a more substantive level, I will first mention that
the book does a good job regarding one of its central proposals, namely
introducing the problem of constitutional interpretation and critically
examining the main existing interpretative theories. To be clear, Sunstein
offers a succinct rather than meticulous examination of those theories, but
this is because his work is mainly directed at people unfamiliar with the
subject. In any case, the book is didactic, and his approach to the subject may
be considered to be well-balanced and well-grounded (although some critics said
that the task Sunstein undertakes, precisely on this point, fails crucially).[5]
In contrast to the above, I think that Sunstein’s
theoretical approach, in this book, is controversial and difficult to sustain. Once
again, my general impression is that, unfortunately, Sunstein throws his theory
into the public forum too soon. In that way, he leaves it at the mercy of
severe and largely avoidable criticisms. More specifically, I believe that the
main analytical tools that he proposes - the "reflective
equilibrium," the "fixed points," the supporting theories
(deliberative democracy, the anti-caste principle) - are hastily and sloppily
presented, which makes his whole theoretical apparatus fragile.
Let me begin by referring to the "supporting
theories" (this is to say, to the last two "fixed points"
presented by the author), namely deliberative democracy and the anti-caste principle.
As I understand it, Sunstein's defense of both issues is in need of a more
careful and robust support. Given the central role that such ideas play in
sustaining his position, one would have expected a less superficial and more
detailed treatment of those issues. Sunstein admits this deficiency in the last
pages of his book. He makes it clear, then, that he is "perfectly
aware" that these two ideas introduced at the end of his work (although
very present in his initial studies) would require much more development. By
way of apology, he mentions that his purpose was to "point in the
direction of such ideas," and to "the centrality" that such
conceptions have regarding "the particular approach to constitutional
law" favored in his book (ibid., 164). We can take these clarifications
for good, of course, but the truth is that recognizing or being fully aware of
the problems that affect a proposition does not strengthen it, nor make it more
rigorous: the deficit remains, and it is a serious deficit.
Just to illustrate my point: one of the main ways in
which Sunstein tries to support the relevance of resorting to those ideas (deliberative
democracy and the anti-caste principle), is by showing the link that would
exist between both conceptions and the roots of American law. However, the
arguments that he presents in this respect are weak and not persuasive:
Sunstein pretends that we take, as generally accepted, too controversial
considerations. Think, for example, about the proposition that "the
founding fathers" adhered to a deliberative understanding of democracy
(which would be contradicted by the more common assumption that they assumed a
"pluralist" or polyarchic conception of democracy). Alternatively,
think about his claim regarding the presence of a strong and egalitarian
version of republicanism, during the founding years (which would be another
highly controversial claim, if we consider that the majority of those founding
fathers were, just to begin, slave-owners).[6] In
sum, such empirical claims are highly controversial. The fact is that
Sunstein's interpretive approach ends up being based on very controversial
assumptions, which should not be presented as if they were not. Much less, if
what he intends to do is present such principles as "fixed points",
widely shared by all members of the community (I will come back to this last
issue below).
Let me add a further note on the character of those
two ideas or principles (deliberative democracy, the anti-caste principle) as
"fixed points" of law. I begin by recalling the following: when
presenting his vision on the "fixed points" of law, Sunstein mentions
certain judicial decisions (such as Brown or Griswold) that all
or almost all of us tend to recognize as benchmarks of American law. Fine. Now,
it is something very different to say, then, that a theory like deliberative
democracy, or a principle like the anti-caste principle, are also "fixed
points" of law. This seems strange.
I claim that the move is strange, first, in relation
to the object of that reflection. The question is: is it appropriate to examine
abstract principles (such as “deliberative democracy” or “the anti-caste
principle”), through the same analytical tools (the "reflective
equilibrium," the "fixed points") that we employ to evaluate the
status of well-known and well-established legal decisions? It does not seem so.
We might for instance say that, after long decades, we have socially converged
in the endorsement of certain particular judicial decisions (Brown).
However, it does not make sense to say the same about a theory of deliberative
democracy or a particular reading of equality. Regarding those issues, it is
difficult to recognize a collective "point of convergence". This,
among other things, because we reflect less, collectively, about them (these
are issues that are not part of our public conversation); but also, because the
levels of disagreement we show on such matters seem much higher. The problem
is, as we shall see, that Sunstein presents his approach, rigorously, in one
form, but also in the opposite form, or open to multiple exceptions, in such a
way that his vision ends up being diffuse and elusive. [7]
Sunstein's approach in this respect is also strange at
a different level: the one related to the subject of this reasoning. The
question is: are we talking about agreements that all or the vast majority of
the members of our legal community seem to have about the law (i.e., we all
think that any reading about the law must be able to recognize the value of a
decision like Brown); or are we referring, instead, to individual
legal criteria, about which we are personally persuaded (i.e., because we are
individually convinced about the value of the theory of deliberative
democracy)?
Between the Theory of Justice and the “chain novel”
This last point helps us to address another question,
more directly related to the method of "reflective equilibrium" -I
mean, “reflective equilibrium” according to the version sponsored at the time
by John Rawls. In his reference to the matter, Rawls did not appeal to -say-
very intense personal preferences or convictions derived from one's philosophy
or ideology. He referred to convictions fundamentally shared by all members of
our community. For that reason, in his references to the subject, Rawls alluded
to examples such as those of religious intolerance and racial discrimination.
What I mean to say is that Rawls referred to issues on which the vast majority
of society seemed to agree fundamentally. In his words (which were written in
the first-person plural):
We are confident that religious intolerance
and racial discrimination are unjust. We have scrutinized these things and have
reached what we believe is an impartial judgment not likely to be distorted by
excessive attention to our interests. These convictions are provisional fixed
points which we presume any conception of justice must fit (Rawls, 1971, pp.
19-20).
Sunstein is well aware of this view (chapter 4).
However, in the ecumenical and conciliatory approach that he develops in the
book, Sunstein suggests a different view on the matter. He presents the matter as if each person
selected his or her “fixed points” and then engaged in a process of “reflective
equilibrium”. He examines these issues as if there were no conclusive reasons
to say that such a conception, such a theory, or such a "fixed point"
were the correct one (for all). For that motive, Sunstein may claim -after he
presented his “own fixed points”: "these propositions are correct...These
are my fixed points; they are part of my reflective equilibrium"
(Sunstein, 2023, p. 161). For him, “each chooser -each one of us- must make a
judgment about what those fixed points are, about exactly how fixed they are,
and about whether one or another approach would endanger them” (ibid., p. 129).
Now: this is not how we usually understand the idea of "reflective
equilibrium," much less is this the way Rawls thought about the question. I
insist: we are not dealing with issues fundamentally related to our personal
preferences or theoretical convictions (where everyone has his views and where
everyone's views, in principle, are equally plausible or reasonable). More
specifically: when Rawls says that “we are confident that religious intolerance
and racial discrimination are unjust” he is not thinking about those problems
as a matter of “choice”. On the contrary, he is thinking of (something like)
the collective recognition or acknowledgement of a problem that is common to
all -a problem that is evident to all. The problem at stake is of such an
entity that everyone can confidently point to it as a serious problem. In
other words, it is not a debatable issue, about which, as Sunstein suggests, we
have to "anticipate and offer convincing responses to
counterarguments" (Sunstein 2023, p. 128). In fact, if these were highly
debatable questions (if we had to make such intellectual efforts in order to
persuade others about the importance of such problems), we would not be talking
of "fixed points" in Rawls's terms.
I have said something about Sunstein's approach to
"fixed points" and its relation to Rawls's theory of justice, and now
I want to say something about that theoretical approach and Ronald Dworkin’s
theory of interpretation. I am thinking, in particular, of the interpretive
theory presented by Dworkin in terms of the "chain novel." As we
know, Dworkin’s “chain-novel-approach” to legal interpretation suggest that the
task before the interpreter of the law is similar to that of the one who
participates in the writing of a "chain novel" (Dworkin, 1986). To summarize
Dworkin’s view in a nutshell: to do his or her job correctly, the participant
in the "chain novel" must "look back," read what has
already been written by previous participants, make sense of what has been
written by all, and then determine what the "best possible
continuation" of that collective novel is- a continuation that is capable
of "accommodating" in the best way all that has already been written.
In law, the (interpretative) task would (should) demand a similar intellectual
exercise: the judge or interpreter looks back and seeks to make sense of all
the written law to then determine what is the best possible continuation of
that law, in the specific case under examination (a decision that “fits” with
the past legal history). His decision, in that specific case, must
"fit" well, in Dworkin's terms, with what has been decided so far by
the legal community, read in "its best light." Or, to put it another
way, that decision must fit with what Sunstein calls "fixed points"
(it must make sense of Brown, Griswold, the
rejection of Lochner, etc.). The point is, so far,
that in spite of the differences that separate the two authors (and perhaps
despite Sunstein's own intentions), there are important points of coincidence
between Dworkin’ and Sunstein’s work in the area. Among other coincidences, i) both
authors are interested in the constructive interpretation of social practices; ii)
both relate constitutional interpretation to an analysis of the community’s
legal history; iii) both pay special attention to paradigmatic judicial
decisions; and iv) both seek to reconstruct that legal history through a
normatively charged approach.
Now, I was interested in drawing attention to the
(non-expected) coincidences that appear between the two authors but, above all,
in highlighting the crucial differences that exist between their approaches.
First of all, while Sunstein seeks to derive, from his proposed "fixed
points," the choice of an "interpretative theory," Dworkin seeks
to derive, simply, the resolution of a concrete case. For example, faced with a
case in which an affirmative action law is challenged, Dworkin might say that
it is appropriate to uphold - rather than invalidate - that law if it can be
demonstrated that this particular decision – say, the defense of a certain
affirmative action measure - makes it possible to give an appropriate account
of Brown and a whole saga of cases were racial equality, the
dignity of the person, and so on, were sustained. My impression is that the
enterprise undertaken by Dworkin (inferring the resolution of a case, from a
well-established legal tradition) is much more natural and reasonable than that
proposed by Sunstein (deducing the choice of an interpretive theory, from
certain "fixed points").
The task proposed by Dworkin is more
"natural" and reasonable, because it relates well to practices that
most members of the legal community engage in, in one way or another. In fact
-I submit- we usually think about the decision of a particular case, taking
into account (in a more or less sophisticated way) legal decisions that have
been made in the past, in similar cases or circumstances. We may or may not adhere
to this approach (take it as our preferred approach) but it refers us to a task
that in no way seems strange to us. Sunstein's proposal, on the other hand,
appears as less "natural", if not directly counter-intuitive. For
him, “the search for reflective equilibrium” plays a central role in constitutional
law. “In fact” -he claims- “it is the only game in town”: “we cannot pull a
theory of the sky, insist that it must be right, and declare victory” (Sunstein
2023, p. 11). But here, again, Sunstein seems to be mixing things up. We can
affirm with him that, somehow, some kind of "reflexive equilibrium"
plays "a central role in constitutional law". But that does not lead
us to conclude, by any means, that this exercise of "reflective
equilibrium" is the one we set in motion "in deciding how to interpret
the Constitution" (or, even more strongly, when “choosing” the best
interpretative theory). Those are two completely different claims. In fact, he
still needs to convince us that we tend to look to past paradigmatic decisions
in order to “choose” an interpretative theory. In other words, this does not
seem to be the way in which we usually come to “defend” a certain theory of
constitutional interpretation. The question is: Do we first “choose” or
define, say, certain paradigmatic judicial decisions, in order to then “choose”
an interpretative theory? Or is the exercise at stake rather the reverse? Most
probably, the interpretative theory that Sunstein claims to find "at the
end of the road" was already present from the very beginning. So,
Sunstein’s proposal in this regard seems to be not only unusual but also
unreasonable if not simply wrong.
In fact, Dworkin could rightly point out that the
theory now in question (the one that Sunstein seeks to derive from history)
pre-existed the proposed exercise. We assume a theory of constitutional
interpretation that first tells us to pay attention to certain "fixed
points"; then helps us to "choose" or recognize some "fixed
points" from our long legal history (say, take up Brown, discard Lochner);
and then induces us to organize them in a certain way, or to derive from them
other conclusions. In sum: the theory is the one that marks all the way from
the beginning, not the one we choose or find at the end of the road.
Through this brief review, I wanted to celebrate the
publication of Cass Sunstein's How to Interpret the Constitution. This
is a book that - on a personal level - reconciles me with an author that I have
followed and admired during decades. Beyond the differences noted, I applaud
what appears to be a "return to the sources" on the part of Sunstein.
And I do so with the hope of encountering new works by the author, reflecting
on constitutional law from a perspective committed to democracy, equality and
social justice.
BIBLIOGRAFIA
Breyer, S. (2011), Making Our Democracy Work, New
York: Vintage.
Dworkin, R. (1977), Taking Rights Seriously,
Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, R. (1986), Law’s Empire, Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Elster, J. (1986) “The Market and the Forum”, en J.
Elster & A. Hylland (eds.), Foundations of social choice theory,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1986, 103 132.
Ely, J. (1980), Democracy and Distrust, Cambridge,
Harvard University Press.
Habermas, J. (1988), Between Facts and Norms,
Cambridge, The MIT Press.
Holloway, C. (2024), “The Great Constitutional Divide”,
The National Review. Magazine, https://www.nationalreview.com/magazine/2024/01/the-great-constitutional-divide/
Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Sunstein, C. (1984) "Naked Preferences and the
Constitution," 84 Columbia Law Review 1689.
Sunstein, C. (1988) “Beyond the Republican Revival”,
97 Yale L. J. 1539.
Sunstein, C. (1990), After the Rights Revolution, Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Sunstein, C. (1993), The Partial Constitution,
Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
Sunstein, C. (1994), “The Anticaste Principle,” Mich.
L. Rev. 92, 2410.
Sunstein, C. (1999) One case at a time. Judicial
minimalism on the Supreme Court, Cambridge, Harvard U.P.
Sunstein, C. (2015), “There is Nothing that
Interpretation Just Is,” Constitutional Commentary 30.
Sunstein, C. (2023), How to interpret the
Constitution, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sunstein, C. &
Vermeule, A. “Interpretation and Institutions,”
101 Mich. L. Rev. 885
(2003).
Thaler, R. & Sunstein, C. (2009), Nudge:
Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness, London: Penguin
Books.
Thayer, J. (1893), “The Origin and Scope of the
American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 7, No.
3 (Oct. 25), pp. 129-156.
Roberto Gargarella. Doctor in Law (University of
Buenos Aires); Jurisprudence Doctor (University of Chicago). CONICET
(Argentina)/ Univ. Pompeu Fabra (Spain)
[1] His introduction in this
regards seems to be heavily based on an article that he published with Adrian
Vermeule, namely “Interpretation and
Institutions” ( https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol101/iss4/2 ) while the views that he
develops in chapter 2 are based on his 2005 article “There is Nothing that
Interpretation Just Is”.
[2] The “separate but equals”
principle established that, as long as the facilities provided to each race
were equal, local governments could require that schools, transportation and
other facilities be segregated by race
[3]
As is well known, the “Thayerist” doctrine arises from a famous work published
by the legal theorist James Brayer Thayer, in 1893, where the jurist maintained
that judicial control can be admitted exclusively in a few cases: in the face
of a “clear mistake”, this is to say when the failure of the norm "is so
clear that it is not open to rational question." (Thayer 1993).
[4]
Let me mention, albeit briefly, a third theoretical commitment that appears
mentioned in the book: the proceduralist reading of constitutional law. This
statement is surprising, in part, given the criticisms that Sunstein used to
direct against this approach (i.e., Sunstein 1993). Indeed, and from the
beginning of his new work, Sunstein proclaims to be "in strong agreement
with the works of John Hart Ely and Stephen Breyer," particularly because
of the emphasis they place on the need for a strong role for judges in the
protection of the preconditions of democratic self-government (ibid., 17).
[5]
In his review of Sunstein’s book, for example, Carson Holloway maintains that
Sunstein’s analysis “fails in its main purposes”, and also that “his denials
are unconvincing”, particularly in what regards the merits of originalist
interpretative theories (Holloway 2024).
[6]
However, and partially denying his immediately previous statements, Sunstein
recognizes that the “republicanism” that he links to the “founding era” was
“patently violated until the Civil War Amendments” Sunstein 2023, 163.
[7]
As usual, Sunstein is not blind to this problem, but he instead deals with it
without much rigor. He emphatically claims, for instance: “It is important to
say that fixed point about constitutional law are not…fixed points about
morality and justice” (Sunstein 2023, p. 13). But, in the very same phrase he
clarifies that what he actually meant to say is that they “are not simply,
fixed points about morality and justice” (ibid., italics added). To add more
complexity (and ambiguity) to the problem, Sunstein admits that “our fixed
points operate at multiple levels of generality” (ibid.), and also that “they
are not only about specific cases”, because they may be “abstract”. In this
way, everything seems to be possible.
1 comentario:
Cass dijo: Say no more!
Publicar un comentario